Skip to main content
Log in

Structure of theory in vegetation science

  • Published:
Vegetatio Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In order to help evaluate progress in vegetation science, we present an outline of the components of theory. Theory has both empirically and conceptually based components, and is tied together by a hierarchical framework. Theory is related to observable phenomena to further the most general goal of science, understanding. More specific tactics to advance understanding include explanation, generalization, and testing. Different components of theory permit the operation of specific tactics. Most components of theory are exemplified by one or more aspects of vegetation science. However, there are some conceptual and empirical components in need of further development. We conclude that vegetation science does in fact conform to the contemporary view of a developing theory, and that this theory can serve as a fruitful guide to research and application of concepts to the field.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • AllenT.F.H. & WileytoE.P. 1983. A hierarchical model for the complexity of plant communities. J. Theor. Biol. 101: 529–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • ArmestoJ.J. & PickettS.T.A. 1986. Removal experiments and the mechanisms of plant succession in old fields. Vegetatio 66: 85–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • AustinM.P. 1980. Searching for a model for use in vegetation analysis. Vegetatio 42: 11–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • AustinM.P. 1986. The theoretical basis of vegetation science. Trends Ecol. Evol.: 1: 161–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • AustinM.P. 1987. Models for the analysis of species' response to environmental gradients. Vegetatio 69: 35–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • BazzazF.A. 1979. The physiological ecology of plant succession. Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 10: 351–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • BazzazF.A. & SipeT.W. 1987. Physiological ecology, disturbance, and ecosystem recovery. In: SchulzeE.-D. & ZwölferH. (eds), Potentials and limitations of ecosystem analysis, pp. 203–227, Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • BrownV.K. 1984. Secondary succession: Insect-plant relationships. BioScience 34: 710–716.

    Google Scholar 

  • ClementsF.E. 1916. Plant succession: An analysis of the development of vegetation. Carnegie Inst. Washington, D.C.

    Google Scholar 

  • ConnellJ.H. & SlatyerR.O. 1977. Mechanisms of succession in natural communities and their role in community stability and organization. Am. Nat. 111: 1119–1144.

    Google Scholar 

  • ConnellJ.H., NobleI.R. & SlatyerR.O. 1987. On the mechanisms producing successional change. Oikos 50: 136–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • DaleM.B. 1980. A syntactic basis for classification. Vegetatio 42: 93–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • GhiselinM.T. 1969. The triumph of the Darwinian method. Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenn-LewinD.C. 1980. The individualistic nature of plant community development. Vegetatio 43: 141–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • GouldS.J. 1986. Evolution and the triumph of homology, or why history matters. Am. Sci. 74: 60–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • GreneM. 1985. Perception, interpretation, and the sciences: Toward a new philosophy of science. In: DepewD.J. & WebberS.H. (eds), Evolution at a crossroads: The new biology and the new philosophy of science, pp. 1–20, MIT Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • HackingI. 1983. Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of science. Cambridge Univ. Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • HustonM. & SmithT. 1987. Plant succession: Life history and competition. Am. Nat. 130: 168–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • JacksonJ.B.C. 1981. Interspecific competition and species distribution: The ghosts of theories and data past. Am. Zool. 21: 889–901.

    Google Scholar 

  • KeddyP.A. 1987. Beyond reductionism and scholasticism in plant community ecology. Vegetatio 69: 209–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • LloydE.A. 1983. The nature of Darwin's support for the theory of natural selection. Phil. Sci. 50: 112–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • LloydE.A. 1987. Confirmation of ecological and evolutionary models. Biol. Phil. 2: 277–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • LoehleC. 1987a. Hypothesis testing in ecology: Psychological aspects and the importance of theory maturation. Quart. Rev. Biol. 62: 397–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • LoehleC. 1987b. Errors of construction, evaluation, and inference: A classification of sources of error in ecological models. Ecol. Modelling 36: 297–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • MayR.M. 1981. The role of theory in ecology. Am. Zool. 21: 903–910.

    Google Scholar 

  • MayR.M. & SegerJ. 1986. Ideas in ecology. Am. Sci. 74: 256–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDonnellM.J. 1988. Landscapes, birds and plants: Dispersal patterns and vegetation change. In: DownhowerJ. (ed.), Biogeography of the Island Region of western Lake Erie, pp. 214–220, Ohio State Univ. Press, Columbus.

    Google Scholar 

  • MillerR.W. 1987. Fact and method: Explanation, confirmation and reality in the natural and social sciences. Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • NagelE. 1961. The structure of science. Harcourt, Brace and World, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • PickettS.T.A. 1983. Absence of an Andropogon stage in oldfield succession at the Hutcheson Memorial Forest. Bull. Torrey Bot. Club 110: 533–535.

    Google Scholar 

  • PickettS.T.A. 1989. Space-for-time substitution as an alternative to long-term studies. In: LikensG.E. (ed.), Long-term studies in ecology: Approaches and alternatives, pp. 110–135. Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • PickettS.T.A., KolasaJ., ArmestoJ.J. & CollinsS.L. 1989. The ecological concept of disturbance and its expression at different hierarchical levels. Oikos 54: 129–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • PielouE.C. 1981. The usefulness of ecological models: A stock taking. Quart. Rev. Biol. 56: 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • PignattiS. 1980. Reflections on the phytosociological approach and the epistemological basis of vegetation science. Vegetatio 42: 181–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • PopperK.R. 1968. Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. Harper, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prentice, I.C. & van der Maarel, E. (eds) 1987. Theory and models in vegetation science. Vegetatio 69: 1–223.

  • RobertsD.W. 1987. A dynamical systems perspective on vegetation theory. Vegetatio 69: 29–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • RosenbergA. 1985. The structure of biological science. Cambridge Univ. Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • RuseM. 1979. Falsifiability, consilience, and synthesis. Syst. Zool. 28: 530–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • SalmonW.C. 1984. Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • SchoenerT.W. 1986. Overview: Kinds of ecological communities-Ecology becomes pluralistic. In: DiamondJ. & CaseT.J. (eds), Community ecology, pp. 467–479, Harper and Row, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • ScrivenM. 1959. Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory. Science 130: 477–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • ShipleyB. & KeddyP.A. 1987. The individualistic and community-unit concepts as falsifiable hypotheses. Vegetatio 69: 47–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • ShugartH.H. 1984. A theory of forest dynamics: The ecological implications of forest succession models. Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • SimonH.A. 1973. The organization of complex systems. In: PatteeH.H. (ed.), Hierarchy theory: The challenge of complex systems, pp. 1–27, Braziler, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • SjörsH. 1980. An arrangement of changes along gradients, with examples from successions in boreal peatland. Vegetatio 43: 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • StegmüllerW. 1976. The structure and dynamics of theories. Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • SuppeF. 1977. Afterword-1977. In: SuppeF. (ed.), The structure of scientific theories, pp. 617–728, Univ. Illinois Press, Urbana.

    Google Scholar 

  • terBraakC.J.F. & PrenticeI.C. 1988. A theory of gradient analysis. Advances Ecol. Res. 18: 271–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • TilmanD. 1982. Resource competition and community structure. Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • van derMaarelE. 1988. Vegetation dynamics: patterns in space and time. Vegetatio 77: 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • van derMaarelE. & WergerM.J.A. 1978. On the treatment of successional data. Phytocoenosis 7: 257–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • van derPijlL. 1972. Principles of dispersal of higher plants, 2nd ed. Springer-Verlag, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • vanHulstR. 1980. Vegetation dynamics or ecosystem dynamics: Dynamic sufficiency in succession theory. Vegetatio 43: 147–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • WalkerL.R. & ChapinIIIF.S. 1987. Interaction among processes controlling successional change. Oikos 50: 131–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • WesthoffV. & van derMaarelE. 1973. The Braun-Blanquet approach. In: WhittakerR.H. (ed.), Ordination and classification of communities, pp. 617–726. Junk, The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pickett, S.T.A., Kolasa, J. Structure of theory in vegetation science. Vegetatio 83, 7–15 (1989). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00031677

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00031677

Keywords

Navigation